Requirements: A paper of 1500 words (minimum word count—any paper more than 150 words short of this minimum will not be accepted as a complete paper). There is no maximum. You may use whatever...

1 answer below »
You can choose the reference/citation format. Must include some references! Doesn't say how much, but include a few should be expected.copy and paste this on the search bar to get more resources to help on this paper:https://drive.google.com/drive/u/0/folders/1RQhjtgBkQCFFEBDJ2peDrzixeXuaOB5S


if that link doesn't work, try this one:https://drive.google.com/drive/folders/1RQhjtgBkQCFFEBDJ2peDrzixeXuaOB5S


Requirements: A paper of 1500 words (minimum word count—any paper more than 150 words short of this minimum will not be accepted as a complete paper). There is no maximum. You may use whatever citation format you wish (MLA, Chicago, etc.) but you MUST HAVE REFERENCES. There is no minimum or maximum number required, however. Prompt: Choose what you believe to be a paradigmatic conceptual framework in the history of science covered up to this point in the course. Your argument should refer to the specific stages and concepts Kuhn uses to describe paradigm shifts. (For example, what are some of the key anomalies of the previous paradigm? Which of these anomalies became critical anomalies? What were the specific crises these anomalies generated? How does the new paradigm deal with these?) Your argument should include the following: • why the framework is paradigmatic (i.e., why is it so fundamental that it rose to the level of a 'worldview'?) • how it evolved from the previous paradigm it replaced • specific historical examples of the paradigm’s evolution Microsoft Word - Kuhn_2.docx INTERNATIONAL ENCYCLOPEDIA of UNIFIED SCIENCE The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Second Edition, Enlarged Thomas S. Kuhn VOLUMES I AND II • FOUNDATIONS OF THE UNITY OF SCIENCE VOLUME II • NUMBER 2 International Encyclopedia of Unified Science Editor-in-Chief Otto Neurath Associate Editors Rudolf Carnap Charles Morris Foundations of the Unity of Science (Volumes I—II of the Encyclopedia) Committee of Organization RUDOLF CARNAP CHARLES MORRIS PHILIPP FRANK OTTO NEURATH JOERGEN JOERGENSEN LOUIS ROUGIER Advisory Committee NIELS BOHR R. VON MISES EGON BRUNSWIK G. MANNOURY J. CLAY ERNEST NAGEL JOHN DEWEY ARNE NAESS FEDERIGO ENRIQUES HANS REICHENBACH HERBERT FEIGL ABEL REY CLARK L. HULL BERTRAND RUSSELL WALDEMAR KAEMPFFERT L. SUSAN STEBBING VICTOR F. LENZEN ALFRED TARSKI JAN LUKASIEWICZ EDWARD C. TOLMAN WILLIAM M. MALISOFF JOSEPH H. WOODGER THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS, CHICAGO 60637 THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS, LTD., LONDON © 1962, 1970 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. Published 1962. Second Edition, enlarged, 1970 Printed in the United States of America 81 80 79 78 11 10 9 8 ISBN: 0-226-45803-2 (clothbound); 0-226-45804-0 (paperbound) Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 79-107472 International Encyclopedia of Unified Science Volume 2 • Number 2 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Thomas S. Kuhn Contents: PREFACE ...................................................... v I. INTRODUCTION: A ROLE FOR HISTORY ............ 1 II. THE ROUTE TO NORMAL SCIENCE .................... 10 III. THE NATURE OF NORMAL SCIENCE ................. 23 IV. NORMAL SCIENCE AS PUZZLE-SOLVING ........... 35 V. THE PRIORITY OF PARADIGMS .......................... 43 VI. ANOMALY AND THE EMERGENCE OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERIES 52 VII. CRISIS AND THE EMERGENCE OF SCIENTIFIC THEORIES 66 VIII. THE RESPONSE TO CRISIS ................................. 77 IX. THE NATURE AND NECESSITY OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS 92 X. REVOLUTIONS AS CHANGES OF WORLD VIEW ...... 111 XI. THE INVISIBILITY OF REVOLUTIONS ................. 136 XII. THE RESOLUTION OF REVOLUTIONS ................ 144 XIII. PROGRESS THROUGH REVOLUTIONS ................ 160 Postscript-1969 ................................................ 174 iii Preface The essay that follows is the first full published report on a project originally conceived almost fifteen years ago. At that time I was a graduate student in theoretical physics already within sight of the end of my dissertation. A fortunate involvement with an experimental college course treating physical science for the non-scientist provided my first exposure to the history of science. To my complete surprise, that exposure to out-of-date scientific theory and practice radically undermined some of my basic conceptions about the nature of science and the reasons for its special success. Those conceptions were ones I had previously drawn partly from scientific training itself and partly from a long-standing avocational interest in the philosophy of science. Somehow, whatever their pedagogic utility and their abstract plausibility, those notions did not at all fit the enterprise that historical study displayed. Yet they were and are fundamental to many discussions of science, and their failures of verisimilitude therefore seemed thoroughly worth pursuing. The result was a drastic shift in my career plans, a shift from physics to history of science and then, gradually, from relatively straightforward historical problems back to the more philosophical concerns that had initially led me to history. Except for a few articles, this essay is the first of my published works in which these early concerns are dominant. In some part it is an attempt to explain to myself and to friends how I happened to be drawn from science to its history in the first place. My first opportunity to pursue in depth some of the ideas set forth below was provided by three years as a Junior Fellow of the Society of Fellows of Harvard University. Without that period of freedom the transition to a new field of study would have been far more difficult and might not have been achieved. Part of my time in those years was devoted to history of science proper. In particular I continued to study the writings of Alex- Vol. II, No. 2 v Preface andre Koyré and first encountered those of Emile Meyerson, Hélène Metzger, and Anneliese Maier.1 More clearly than most other recent scholars, this group has shown what it was like to think scientifically in a period when the canons of scientific thought were very different from those current today. Though I increasingly question a few of their particular historical interpretations, their works, together with A. O. Lovejoy’s Great Chain of Being, have been second only to primary source materials in shaping my conception of what the history of scientific ideas can be. Much of my time in those years, however, was spent exploring fields without apparent relation to history of science but in which research now discloses problems like the ones history was bringing to my attention. A footnote encountered by chance led me to the experiments by which Jean Piaget has illuminated both the various worlds of the growing child and the process of transition from one to the next.2 One of my colleagues set me to reading papers in the psychology of perception, particularly the Gestalt psychologists; another introduced me to B. L. Whorf’s speculations about the effect of language on world view; and W. V. O. Quine opened for me the philosophical puzzles of the analytic- synthetic distinction.3 That is the sort of random exploration that the Society of Fellows permits, and only through it could I have encountered Ludwik Fleck’s almost unknown monograph, Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wis- 1 Particularly influential were Alexandre Koyré, Études Galiléennes (3 vols.; Paris, 1939); Emile Meyerson, Identity and Reality, trans. Kate Loewenberg (New York, 1930); Hélène Metzger, Les doctrines chimiques en France du début du XVIIe à la fin du XVIIIe siècle (Paris, 1923), and Newton, Stahl, Boerhaave et la doctrine chimique (Paris, 1930); and Anneliese Maier, Die Vorläufer Galileis im 14. Jahrhundert (“Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik”; Rome, 1949). 2 Because they displayed concepts and processes that also emerge directly from the history of science, two sets of Piaget s investigations proved particularly important: The Child’s Conception of Causality, trans. Marjorie Gabain (London, 1930), and Les notions de mouvement et de vitesse
Answered Same DayApr 27, 2022

Answer To: Requirements: A paper of 1500 words (minimum word count—any paper more than 150 words short of this...

Rochak answered on Apr 28 2022
103 Votes
Paradigmatic Conceptual Framework
A paradigm is an assumption about the understanding of the worldview based on the theories which have been identified by the scientific community, and all the experiments and observations surrounding this belief.
The paradigmatic shift is a
popular concept given by the American physicist and philosopher Thomas Kuhn, where the focus was on the fundamental change which we see from the perspective of concepts and experimental practices of a scientific discipline.
The notion and the whole concept of this paradigmatic shift were given to the world by him in his influential book “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962)”.
The Kuhn Cycle
· Normal Science: Normal science is the most prominent stage in science, where according to Kuhn a dominant paradigm is active. The paradigm that is talked about here is the set of theories and the ideas which give the scientists and other researchers a clear definition of what is possible, with certain tools that can be used to approach problems. The examples given by Kuhn in his book are:
· Newtonian Physics
· Theory of Electromagnetism
The whole concept of normal science is where Kuhn stresses that this is the stage where anomalies occur, because two users of an atom may operate with different paradigms (i.e., chemist and physicist). Popular environmentalism is in the pre-science step, but they still assume that they are in the normal science step
· Model Drift: Because there are anomalies, therefore the field of science digs itself to answer the new questions which cannot be answered using the current understanding and science. With the increase in the anomalies because of the no-answer, the whole model grows weaker and gives rise to the model drift step, where the model is losing its worth
· Model Crisis: The actual paradigm shift occurs at this step because the anomalies have started to become serious, and this is where the attempt is made to remove those anomalies because of the constant fail, when this happens new ideas which challenge the existing paradigm are developed. The step is also a boundary where if the anomalies can be resolved they are resolved and the crisis gets over after the resolution, but if not, the scientific revolution occurs which starts the whole change in the paradigm which we also call a paradigm shift
· Model Revolution: The step where the new paradigm is established, this is major because of the psychological and sociological behaviour. The new paradigm which is established is closer to the objectives which were not answered by the existing principles and therefore the anomalies which led to the revolution and the change in the paradigm. One thing to note which was stated by Kuhn is that the new paradigm...
SOLUTION.PDF

Answer To This Question Is Available To Download

Related Questions & Answers

More Questions »

Submit New Assignment

Copy and Paste Your Assignment Here